Proof: By Euclid
(related to Proposition: Prop. 10.009: Commensurability of Squares)

- For since A is commensurable in length with B, A thus has to B the ratio which (some) number (has) to (some) number [Prop. 10.5].
- Let it have (that) which C (has) to D.
- Therefore, since as A is to B, so C (is) to D.
- But the (ratio) of the square on A to the square on B is the square of the ratio of A to B.
- For similar figures are in the squared ratio of (their) corresponding sides [Prop. 6.20 corr.] 5.
- And the (ratio) of the square on C to the square on D is the square of the ratio of the [number] C to the [number] D.
- For there exists one number in mean proportion3 to two square numbers, and (one) square (number) has to the (other) square [number] a squared ratio with respect to (that) the side (of the former has) to the side (of the latter) [Prop. 8.11].
- And, thus, as the square on A is to the square on B, so the square [number] on the (number) C (is) to the square [number] on the [number] D.
- And so let the square on A be to the (square) on B as the square (number) on C (is) to the [square] (number) on D.
- I say that A is commensurable in length with B.
- For since as the square on A is to the [square] on B, so the square (number) on C (is) to the [square] (number) on D.
- But, the ratio of the square on A to the (square) on B is the square of the (ratio) of A to B [Prop. 6.20 corr.] 5.
- And the (ratio) of the square [number] on the [number] C to the square [number] on the [number] D is the square of the ratio of the [number] C to the [number] D [Prop. 8.11].
- Thus, as A is to B, so the [number] C also (is) to the [number] D.
- A, thus, has to B the ratio which the number C has to the number D.
- Thus, A is commensurable in length with B " [Prop. 10.6] ":https://www.bookofproofs.org/branches/magnitudes-with-rational-ratio-are-commensurable/.
- And so let A be incommensurable in length with B.
- I say that the square on A does not have to the [square] on B the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number.
- For if the square on A has to the [square] on B the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number then A will be commensurable (in length) with B.
- But it is not.
- Thus, the square on A does not have to the [square] on the B the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number.
- So, again, let the square on A not have to the [square] on B the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number.
- I say that A is incommensurable in length with B.
- For if A is commensurable (in length) with B then the (square) on A will have to the (square) on B the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number.
- But it does not have (such a ratio).
- Thus, A is not commensurable in length with B.
- Thus, (squares) on (straight lines which are) commensurable in length, and so on ....
∎
Thank you to the contributors under CC BY-SA 4.0!

- Github:
-

- non-Github:
- @Fitzpatrick
References
Adapted from (subject to copyright, with kind permission)
- Fitzpatrick, Richard: Euclid's "Elements of Geometry"
Footnotes