Proof: By Euclid
(related to Proposition: Prop. 10.052: Construction of Fifth Binomial Straight Line)
- For since as $CA$ is to $AB$, so the (square) on $EF$ (is) to the (square) on $FG$, inversely, as $BA$ (is) to $AC$, so the (square) on $FG$ (is) to the (square) on $FE$ [Prop. 5.7 corr.] 1.
- Thus, the (square) on $GF$ (is) greater than the (square) on $FE$ [Prop. 5.14].
- Therefore, let (the sum of) the (squares) on $EF$ and $H$ be equal to the (square) on $GF$.
- Thus, via convertion, as the number $AB$ is to $BC$, so the (square) on $GF$ (is) to the (square) on $H$ [Prop. 5.19 corr.] 2.
- And $AB$ does not have to $BC$ the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number.
- Thus, the (square) on $FG$ does not have to the (square) on $H$ the ratio which (some) square number (has) to (some) square number either.
- Thus, $FG$ is incommensurable in length with $H$ [Prop. 10.9].
- Hence, the square on $FG$ is greater than (the square on) $FE$ by the (square) on (some straight line) incommensurable (in length) with ($FG$).
- And $GF$ and $FE$ are rational (straight lines which are) commensurable in square only.
- And the lesser term $EF$ is commensurable in length with the rational (straight line previously) laid down, $D$.
- Thus, $EG$ is a fifth binomial (straight line).
- (Which is) the very thing it was required to show.
∎
Thank you to the contributors under CC BY-SA 4.0!
- Github:
-
- non-Github:
- @Fitzpatrick
References
Adapted from (subject to copyright, with kind permission)
- Fitzpatrick, Richard: Euclid's "Elements of Geometry"